Thursday, March 24, 2011
Where in the creed does it call for liberalism or conservatism?
Conservatism must remember that the Gospel of Jesus Christ is not only his earthly words but just as equally his actions. Moreover, it was not suffering in itself that is salvific, but Jesus' commitment, obedience, and fidelity through it.
Liberalism must remember that what theology needs is a hermeneutics of faith, not merely a secular hermeneutics of the latest philosophical fad. Liberalism would do good to remember an old medieval limerick regarding how we ought to read scripture: Littera gesta docet, quid credas allegoria, moralis quid agas, quo tendas anagogia. "The letter speaks of deeds, allegory about the faith, the moral about our actions, analogy about our destiny." Let them not neglect our faith and our collective destiny.
The only way to avoid sliding into one extreme or the other is to strive for fidelity in our collective and historical faith. Through adhering to the tradition of our faith we find sustenance to continue onward amongst so many temptations to go astray. The beauty of our faith is that it is historical. It doesn't ask us to believe random notions created by the recent ideological sway in society, lacking any historical credibility like so many self-created religious groups of the last century. But, just as equally it demands of us to remain committed to action, not merely passive in reciting beliefs. It eternally calls us to become more than we are today, it does not allow us the comfort of complacency. The reason why our faith is able to do this is because of the history of countless saints who have come before us and blazed the path in which we follow. Either extreme of liberalism or conservatism neglects part of that historical faith. It either ignores our collective faith and destiny or it neglects our struggle for growth and action.
It does good to remember that the Church does not count time in decades, like our culture does, but in centuries. And we ought to remember that the historical Church is not liberal or conservative, rather it was, is and remains, one, holy, apostolic and catholic.
Saturday, March 19, 2011
Heidegger, Husserl and Thomas Aquinas
Sunday, March 13, 2011
Outdated Versions of Thomism
Transcendental Thomism: Karl Rahner, Bernard Lonergan. These are your typical Neo-Kantians, they tend to be Cartesian dualists (subjectivists) and typically use Thomas in "creative manners," with little regard for the historical character of actual Thomism.
Analytical Thomism: Kretzmann, Stump. These are your philosophers who want to use the name of Thomas, and some of his ideas, to address issues within analytic philosophy.
Existential Thomism: Gilson, Maritain. These philosophers tend to be more influenced by continental philosophy, yet unlike the transcendentals are not "card carrying" Neo-Kantians. They want to use parts of Thomas for problems within continental philosophy.
Aristotelian Thomism: These are your philosophers who tend to emphasize the historical Thomas, as well as his reliance on Aristotelianism. These tend to be your medievalists, interested in history and ecclesial tradition.
Yet, I'm becoming more and more convinced that these are outdated models of Thomism. I would like to offer a more up to date divison of Thomism in the 21st century:
Fribourg (German) Thomism: These philosophers seem to have little regard for the historical problems that Thomas himself was interested in. They tend to read Thomas alone and neither apply it to contemporary issues or analyze the historical nexus of his work.
Angelicum Thomism: These philosophers tend to place all their interest in the historical Thomas. It tends to stress the originality of Thomas and underplays his Aristotelian reliance.
Pseudo-Analytical Thomism: These philosophers tend to give no credence whatsoever to the original Thomas and its historicality. It seems many times they merely pick and choose whatever suits their contemporary needs.
Finally, what I'm interested in
Historical and Contemporary Thomism: These philosophers merge the Angelicum thomism with the old existential thomism with modest results. I believe there is potential in this, but it needs to be broader. This type of Thomism needs to have the historical rigor of the Angelicum, but the agility to bring into discussion both existential thomism and a form of analytic philosophy. Both on their own tends to lead to ridiculous grandstanding to particular needs given to their respective philosophical stem (continental or analytic).
So using the old versions, you could say I want to merge all three camps, minus the transcendental thomists who I believe we can just ditch by the roadside. But if using this newer model, we need to ditch the pseudo-analytic thomism which seems to do nothing whatsoever in regards to what Thomas actually said, yet at the same time not ignore analytic problems. We need a thomism which is firmly rooted in the actual person of Thomas, yet with the ability to consistentantly and cogently speak to the continentals and analytics. Its a tough task, but it must be done. As it is now, Thomism is too fractured.
Tuesday, March 08, 2011
Commentary on The Old System-Program of German Idealism
Wednesday, March 02, 2011
Kantian Epistemology: What Can We Know and How?
There is perhaps no more influential epistemology on post Enlightenment philosophy than Kant, certainly there is at the very least no more influential modern philosopher. While the critical philosophy of Kant undoubtedly affected almost every discipline within philosophy, perhaps none were as radically altered by his critiques than the discipline of epistemology (although, as Fr. Schenk reminds us, where we jump in may not turn out as important as how we decide to proceed). Nevertheless, in arguing for a Copernican revolution in philosophy, Kant, to his mind, attempted to synthesize the empiricists and rationalists. Whereas the empiricists attempted to begin epistemological inquiry through an objective knowledge of an external world, Kant believed that it was the subject itself that imposes on the external world certain categories and knowledge. To be sure, one could make a reasonable argument that Kant was merely bringing Cartesian dualism to its logical conclusion. Where Descartes understood the relationship between the res cogitans and the res extensa as possible through interactionism in the pineal gland, Kant understood such an interaction was impossible. In this way Kant brought the Cartesian compromise to its skeptical completion, exposing the logical error Descartes was never able to fully appreciate, namely that no matter where such an interactionism is located the subject can never be fully able to know the res extensa as it really exists. The res cogitans could never penetrate the res extensa. The correspondence between knower and thing known was crushed under the weight of the knower’s subjectivity, and along with it all of metaphysics.
Most fundamental to Kantian epistemology is the distinction between analytic judgments and synthetic judgments. Analytical judgments are based on the law of non-contradiction, knowledge intuitively known through immediate inference. Specifically, such knowledge is a tautology, the information gleaned from analyzing the terminology. Moreover, such knowledge is a priori, that is, knowledge which is independent upon experience. On the other hand, synthetic judgments provide us with new knowledge of the world and rely on the ability to synthesize the subject with the predicate. In this manner, synthetic judgments form the bedrock of reason, forming the ability to rationally progress through logical statements. Moreover, synthetic judgments, according to Kant, are both a priori and a posteriori. As a priori judgments, synthetic knowledge is obtained independent from external experience of the subject. Juxtaposed with this, a posteriori judgments are gleaned from interaction with the external world of sensation. In a priori judgments, the more controversial distinction, Kant argues that there are judgments which give us knowledge of the world, but through a priori means. This might sound counter-intuitive, but for Kant it is a vital distinction for his understanding of mathematical judgments and judgments about phenomena which can never be universalized by pure observation. For example, ‘all events have a cause’ is not empirically based, we can never verify it through direct observation, yet we bring it to our presuppositions of the external world.
Another vital Kantian move in epistemology is the distinction between the phenomena and noumena. As mentioned above, the Copernican revolution for Kant requires that the human subject be understood as the beginning point for knowledge. We can never escape our limitations, positions, and subjectivity to stand outside ourselves and judge our interaction between self and external world. Hence, for Kant the ‘I think’ is the subjective condition for knowledge, which by definition can never be an objective condition. In this regard, Kant rejects both the empiricist and rationalist positions. Rationalists tend to believe there is a world which exists as a limited whole, a space/time condition in which the self exists. Empiricists tend to believe the world is unlimited, externally verifiable through proper observation. By rejecting both positions, Kant’s Copernican turn supplants both positions by arguing that the world is not an object ‘out there.’ Rather, our subjective condition allows for knowledge to come to the knower, but in a confused fashion, ultimately determined by categorization by the mind. Hence, Kant determines that there is a division between that which exists in its reality, the noumena, and that which comes to us in our subjective condition, determined by the mind’s categories, namely the phenomena.
Moreover, for Kant, the only manner in which the subjective self can have knowledge of the external world is through the phenomenon, never the noumena. However, Kant does not want to collapse into a complete solipsism in which the external world is in complete chaos, relative and lacking reality. Even though the cognitive subject can never know the extended world as it really exists, the appearance of that reality as the phenomenon is in some manner caused by the noumena. For Kant this is possible because causation is not an empirically verifiable principle based on direct observation, but rather a category used by the mind in order to structure the phenomena. However, this leaves room for problems in understanding the actual relationship between the noumena and phenomena. If in fact causation is mere mental construction, not a reality-in-and-of-itself, then how can we say with certainty that there is an actual causal relationship between the noumena and the phenomena? Perhaps there is no connection between the two, in which seemingly, Kantian epistemology does indeed slip into solipsism.
We must ask the question, under this epistemological model, what can we know? Seemingly, for Kant, the only knowledge available to the subject is the phenomenon. While he retains his position of the two stems of knowledge, empiricism and rationalism, both seem muted by the distinction between appearance and reality. If the phenomena are mere constructive structures determined by the mind, then reality, and knowledge of it, will always be elusive. Under such a model, only the appearance of such reality can be readily accepted into our noetical structure. But, perhaps more interesting, especially when held to the light of the history of philosophy, is Kant’s rejection of metaphysical knowledge, a clear result of the above distinction. The best metaphysics can achieve under such a narrow epistemological justification are transcendent illusions. Mirroring the noumena and phenomena distinction, Kant allows for the limitations of the transcendental and transcendent. Transcendent knowledge, under this view, is by definition beyond the ability of the human subject, while the best our cognitive advances can hope for is merely transcendental.
There seem to be several major outcomes of such a narrow epistemology that the history of philosophy has reasonably proved. First, when the noumena, or transcendent, is removed from even the possibility of knowledge and instead understood as the limitations of knowledge, metaphysics is completely removed from philosophical inquiry. The ramifications of such a removal are too vast for this brief summary, but certainly ought not to be overlooked. Second, such an epistemological model centers on the subjective ‘I,’ starting the epistemological process with the condition of a something relative to the subject, namely existence. Operating within such an internal psychological state, it is no wonder Kant has such a problem with the transcendent. Moreover, by limiting the self as ultimately elusive and unknowable the self becomes itself a phenomenon, merely an appearance of the noumena. And, under such a position, it would seemingly be impossible to ever gain knowledge of that subjective self in relation to others or objects, as others and objects would also be mere phenomena, in which case it would be impossible to even postulate the noumena.