Saturday, December 17, 2011
Pythagorean Quote
---Pythagoras
Tuesday, December 06, 2011
Antony Flew, Atheism
Luther and The Foundation of Protestantism
Here is the part about Luther's justification bringing righteousness. But notice it is only after we have been declared righteous by God, we have done nothing ourselves. This needs to be seen as a direct assault against the Church's position that we are sacramentally imbued with an indeliable mark. Moreover, there is no change in the person via declaration, the change is "in alio ad caelum" or assumed in heaven. This needs to be seen as an assault on the Church's position that there is also a visible Church, not merely an invisible Church. Here we can see the foundation forming of Protestantism's complete individualism, lack of sacramental change, lack of salvific participation, and rejection of habitual virtues (i.e. virtues that are natural and not supernatural). Its a house of cards, you take down the bottom the whole thing collapses.
DiNoia, Postmodern Thomism and its Failures
DiNoia finds several interesting roles for the existence of God which intend to remove the typical rejections they receive from typically modern critiques, such as the Kantian undercutting of metaphysics. DiNoia argues that one role for traditional arguments, which can be found even in Thomas Aquinas and his “Five Ways,” is that these arguments should be understood as internal expressions of the ecclesial life, and not as rigid apologetics that ought to be used to combat modern critiques. For example, Thomas’ “Five Ways,” are not merely apologetic but also, “Rather, such arguments function to locate Christian worship, nurture, practice, and belief on the widest possible conceptual map: the God who is adored, proclaimed, and confessed in the Christian Church is none other than the cause of the world.” Hence, DiNoia places the Thomistic arguments for God in what we might now call an existential horizon, as an internal expression of concepts that bring to life the internal world of the liturgy to the real world of causality. Another role that traditional arguments for the existence of God can have, according to DiNoia, is also found in Thomas’ work, namely his use of analogical relations. The appeal of such relations, as I understand it, is that it uses a semantic framework which no longer speaks in what is perceived as univocal and absolute language (although this seems to be a caricature of medieval thought), and instead embraces a more nuanced approach that keeps in mind the limitless gulf between created and creator, and hence between object and subject. One can see the appeal of this to a postmodern audience, as it directly appeases a hermeneutical horizon that seeks a larger role for enculturation and subjectivity, and distresses the more ontological and objective role of arguments. With this said, one can still ask the question, is this “postmodern-friendly” role for Thomas’ arguments really what Thomas himself had in mind? If not, and I think there is good reason to question if it is, then using postmodernism’s own caution for the subjective context of place and situation, one would assume that such a re-appropriation of Thomas’ work undercuts his own historicality and neglects the very subjectivity that such a postmodern approach seeks to preserve.
Monday, May 09, 2011
Existence and Essence
An important element of Thomistic metaphysics is the role of existence and essence. Within creatures there is a distinction which must be made between existence and essence. However for God, his essence is his existence. This is important to note because many theological and philosophical errors have derived from a failure to recognize these two distinctions.
First, within creatures existence and essence cannot be convertible. Every material substance, (spiritual substances differ slightly) is the combination of a substantial form and matter. Hence, each individual material substance has an individuating principle, namely matter, and a universal quiddity which provides its nature, namely its substantial form. This is required for twofold reasons which are relevant for our discussion. First, a substantial form provides a material substance with its nature, providing its regular functions and its limitations. Second, a substantial form actualizes primary matter, yet secondary matter still remains which leaves open possibilities for the material substance to change. Hence, this hylomorphic understanding of material substances allows for the necessity of all things to change. Moreover, this change is only possible because the secondary matter which exists in the material substance, allowing for the potential of a substantial change. This can only occur if within material substances, both existence and essence are not convertible. If existence and essence were convertible within created material substances, then there would be no change possible within substances. In other words, we would be left with a complete monism, not unlike Spinoza. This is obviously in error because it cannot account for a plurality of beings or substantial change, nor ultimately the distinction between creator and created. Hence, from the above we can conclude that in material substances there is a real distinction between essence and existence.
Second, within God, his essence must be his existence. According to Thomas, God is that which necessarily is. Moreover, if that which is was different than his existence, than that essence would be in variance with his existence, as in a quality which is in variance with its substance. However this is impossible in God, because that would create a division with the Godhead, which is a logical impossibility as that which necessarily is, is also necessarily one. In other words, if God has an essence which was different than his existence, then there would be a division in God between what he is and that he is. Moreover, this division has several repercussions that lead to error. First, such a division would mean that God’s essence was dependent upon his existence, which would mean that within God was something dependent, not pure actuality. Second, such a division would mean that God’s essence was something superadded to his existence, and hence something would need to be posited outside of God which can then can add into God his essence, which is a clear absurdity. Third, if there was a division between God’s essence and existence, it would mean that there could be change within God. As I mentioned above, the reason that material substances can change is because there is a separation between our existence and essence, which can account for a potentiality to be something other than we are. However, if this was also the case with God, it would mean that God had a potentiality to be something other than he is, in which case he could also change who he is to be something else. This is obviously absurd, as it violates the principle that God is pure act, changeless and perfect. Finally and ultimately, if God’s essence and existence were different, we would logically have to posit a God above God. This is because if God had potentiality and thus not pure act, we would have to ask the question, where did God get his potentiality from, except from that which is pure act and which can have no distinctions? Hence, from the above, there can be no distinction between existence and essence in God.
Wednesday, April 06, 2011
Heidegger vs Thomas Aquinas
Martin Heidegger in his Marburg lectures, Introduction to Phenomenological Research, broadly attempts to trace phenomenology through the history of philosophy. Through the course of Heidegger’s search for phenomenology (with an emphasis on ontology) within the philosophical tradition he analyzes Thomas Aquinas’ determination of truth laid forth in De veritate. Heidegger principally examines the first question, articles 1-3 and 9 in attempt to demonstrate that Thomas laid the groundwork for the later Cartesian belief that the primordial grounding of truth is located in the res cogitans. It is the Thomistic understanding of truth which, according to Heidegger, leads the philosophical tradition toward the individualist appropriation of ontology that we find in modernity. Hence, my research consists of Heidegger’s specific argument against Thomas in his commentary on De veritate, as well as the ramifications of such an interpretation among the broader scholarly dialogue that has been developing between Thomas Aquinas and Heidegger. The thesis of this work consists of a critique of the Heideggerian interpretation of Thomas in his commentary on De veritate, question 1, articles 1-3 and 9. Moreover, this work has a twofold aim, namely to draw out the potential Heideggerian misinterpretation of Thomas’ determination of truth within De veritate, as well as situating such an argument within the larger scope of the interpenetrating dialogue of Thomistic and Heideggerian ontology. The audience of such a work are those interested in a potential dialogue between Thomism and Heideggerian ontology, a dialogue that exposes a latent misinterpretation on the part of Heidegger, yet not without the potential to expose possible commonalities.
Thursday, March 24, 2011
Where in the creed does it call for liberalism or conservatism?
Conservatism must remember that the Gospel of Jesus Christ is not only his earthly words but just as equally his actions. Moreover, it was not suffering in itself that is salvific, but Jesus' commitment, obedience, and fidelity through it.
Liberalism must remember that what theology needs is a hermeneutics of faith, not merely a secular hermeneutics of the latest philosophical fad. Liberalism would do good to remember an old medieval limerick regarding how we ought to read scripture: Littera gesta docet, quid credas allegoria, moralis quid agas, quo tendas anagogia. "The letter speaks of deeds, allegory about the faith, the moral about our actions, analogy about our destiny." Let them not neglect our faith and our collective destiny.
The only way to avoid sliding into one extreme or the other is to strive for fidelity in our collective and historical faith. Through adhering to the tradition of our faith we find sustenance to continue onward amongst so many temptations to go astray. The beauty of our faith is that it is historical. It doesn't ask us to believe random notions created by the recent ideological sway in society, lacking any historical credibility like so many self-created religious groups of the last century. But, just as equally it demands of us to remain committed to action, not merely passive in reciting beliefs. It eternally calls us to become more than we are today, it does not allow us the comfort of complacency. The reason why our faith is able to do this is because of the history of countless saints who have come before us and blazed the path in which we follow. Either extreme of liberalism or conservatism neglects part of that historical faith. It either ignores our collective faith and destiny or it neglects our struggle for growth and action.
It does good to remember that the Church does not count time in decades, like our culture does, but in centuries. And we ought to remember that the historical Church is not liberal or conservative, rather it was, is and remains, one, holy, apostolic and catholic.
Saturday, March 19, 2011
Heidegger, Husserl and Thomas Aquinas
Sunday, March 13, 2011
Outdated Versions of Thomism
Transcendental Thomism: Karl Rahner, Bernard Lonergan. These are your typical Neo-Kantians, they tend to be Cartesian dualists (subjectivists) and typically use Thomas in "creative manners," with little regard for the historical character of actual Thomism.
Analytical Thomism: Kretzmann, Stump. These are your philosophers who want to use the name of Thomas, and some of his ideas, to address issues within analytic philosophy.
Existential Thomism: Gilson, Maritain. These philosophers tend to be more influenced by continental philosophy, yet unlike the transcendentals are not "card carrying" Neo-Kantians. They want to use parts of Thomas for problems within continental philosophy.
Aristotelian Thomism: These are your philosophers who tend to emphasize the historical Thomas, as well as his reliance on Aristotelianism. These tend to be your medievalists, interested in history and ecclesial tradition.
Yet, I'm becoming more and more convinced that these are outdated models of Thomism. I would like to offer a more up to date divison of Thomism in the 21st century:
Fribourg (German) Thomism: These philosophers seem to have little regard for the historical problems that Thomas himself was interested in. They tend to read Thomas alone and neither apply it to contemporary issues or analyze the historical nexus of his work.
Angelicum Thomism: These philosophers tend to place all their interest in the historical Thomas. It tends to stress the originality of Thomas and underplays his Aristotelian reliance.
Pseudo-Analytical Thomism: These philosophers tend to give no credence whatsoever to the original Thomas and its historicality. It seems many times they merely pick and choose whatever suits their contemporary needs.
Finally, what I'm interested in
Historical and Contemporary Thomism: These philosophers merge the Angelicum thomism with the old existential thomism with modest results. I believe there is potential in this, but it needs to be broader. This type of Thomism needs to have the historical rigor of the Angelicum, but the agility to bring into discussion both existential thomism and a form of analytic philosophy. Both on their own tends to lead to ridiculous grandstanding to particular needs given to their respective philosophical stem (continental or analytic).
So using the old versions, you could say I want to merge all three camps, minus the transcendental thomists who I believe we can just ditch by the roadside. But if using this newer model, we need to ditch the pseudo-analytic thomism which seems to do nothing whatsoever in regards to what Thomas actually said, yet at the same time not ignore analytic problems. We need a thomism which is firmly rooted in the actual person of Thomas, yet with the ability to consistentantly and cogently speak to the continentals and analytics. Its a tough task, but it must be done. As it is now, Thomism is too fractured.